Let me focus on the question of your title, and mention
that there is another quite robust way to understand what
it means to say that a random Turing machine has
such-and-such property.
Specifically, we use the concept of asymptotic density as
the size of the program increases. For any natural number
n, there are only finitely many Turing machine program
using n states. The asymptotic density or asymptotic probability
of a set A of Turing machine programs is the limit (if it
exists)
- limntoinftyfrac|AcapPn||Pn|,
where Pn is finite the set of Turing machine programs
with exactly n states. Thus, the asymptotic probability
of a set A of Turing machine programs is simply the limit
of the proportion of n-state programs in A. In
particular, if a set A has asymptotic density 1, then
it means that more than 99, more than 99.9, of
Turing machine programs are in A, as close to 1 as
desired as the number of states increases. In this case, we
would seem to be justified in saying that almost every
Turing machine program is in A.
One can interpret your title question this way as
inquiring: what is the asymptotic density of the set of
Turing machine programs that decide sets that are
equivalent to a DFA?
To give an elementary sample calculation, a Turing machine
program p in finite alphabet Sigma with states S
(not counting the halt state) is a function
SigmatimesStoSigmatimes(Scuphalt)timesL,R. For example, if the alphabet
has 2 symbols and there are n states, then there are
(4(n+1))2n many programs. The number of programs that
never transition to the halt state, however, is
(4n)2n, which has proportion (fracnn+1)2n,
which goes to frac1e2 as ntoinfty. Thus, the
density of programs that never halt at all, because they
can never transition to the halt state, is frac1e2,
or about 13.5. Of course, all such programs decide the
empty language, which is also decided by a DFA, so this is
a lower bound on the title question.
This way of thinking is the foundation of the topic of
generic case
complexity.
A central concern of this topic is the fact that many
undecidable or unfeasible decision problems admit a black
hole, a very small region where the problem is difficult,
outside of which it is easy. For example, it is not good to
base a financial encryption scheme on a problem whose
difficulty is confined to a black hole---a robber is after
all satisfied to rob the bank even only 90 of the time,
or even only 1 of the time. Alexei Miasnikov inquired
whether the halting problem itself admits a black hole, and
it turned out that for one of the standard models of
computability, the answer is yes:
Theorem.(Hamkins+Miasnikov) For the Turing machine
model with one-way infinite tapes, there is a set of Turing
machine programs A such that
- A has asymptotic density 1, so almost every program
is in A. - A is polynomial time decidable.
- The halting problem is polynomial time decidable for
programs in A.
Thus, for this model of computation, the halting problem is
decidable with probability 1. The reason has to do with
the fact that for the one-way infinite tape Turing machine
model, it turns out that almost every Turing machine
program, like Polya's drunken man, falls off the tape
before repeating a state. And this is something that can be
detected in linear time. It follows that with asymptotic
probability one, a Turing machine program computes a finite
set. Since all finite sets are DFA computable, we conclude:
Corollary. For the standard one-way infinite tape
model of Turing machines, with asymptotic probability one,
a random Turing machine computes a set that is DFA
decidable.
See J. D. Hamkins, A. Miasnikov, The halting problem is
decidable on a set of asymptotic probability
one, Notre Dame Journal
of Formal Logic, Notre Dame J. Formal Logic 47 (2006),
515–524.
See also this MO
answer,
which mentions similar ideas.
No comments:
Post a Comment